Scientific Methods, Birth Of Modern

Birth Of Modern Scientific Methods, Bacon And Descartes

Author: Lewes, George Henry

1620

Three centuries of modern thought have not sufficed to settle the dispute

as to its own origin. Many Englishmen still claim insistently that Lord

Bacon, in his Advancement of Learning, and still more positively in his later

and greater work, the Novum Organum (1620) started modern scientific method.

Present scientists themselves seem inclined to smile somewhat scornfully at

the laurels thus placed on Bacon's brow. And as for Frenchmen, they simply

refuse to hear the pompous Lord Chancellor mentioned at all. To them Rene

Descartes is the only genuine originator of all modern philosophy. The

publication of his Discourse on Method (1637) marks for them the epoch which

separates two worlds of thought.

Fortunately, George Henry Lewes, himself a celebrated English critic and

the author of a system of philosophy, presents us the two rivals side by side,

seeking to explain and balance the honors due to each.

It is very certain that somewhere about this period did originate that

mathematical exactitude of method in both thought and experiment which has

produced modern science. And modern science has, in its brief but marvellous

career of three centuries, altered the face of the globe. It has taught man

more than ancient science did in all the preceding centuries; it has touched

even our deepest faiths.

Whether its success has been due mainly to the abstract reasoners like

Copernicus and the philosophers, or to the practical experimenters like

Galileo and Harvey, is perhaps scarcely a practical question.

In the evolution of philosophy, as in the evolution of an organism, it is

impossible to fix with any precision a period of origin, because every

beginning is also a termination, and presumes the results of a whole series of

preceding evolutions. As Mr. Spedding felicitously says, our philosophy "was

born about Bacon's time, and Bacon's name, as the brightest which presided at

the time of its birth, has been inscribed upon it:

"Hesperus that led

The starry host rode brightest."

"Not that Hesperus did actually lead the other stars; he and they were moving

under a common force, and they would have moved just as fast if he had been

away; but because he shone brightest, he looked as if he led them." Bacon and

Descartes are generally recognized as the "Fathers of Modern Philosophy,"

though they themselves were carried along by the rapidly swelling current of

their age, then decisively setting in the direction of science. It is their

glory to have seen visions of the coming greatness, to have expressed in terms

of splendid power the thoughts which were dimly stirring the age, and to have

sanctioned the new movement by their authoritative genius. The destruction of

scholasticism was complete. They came to direct the construction of a grander

temple.

There are in these two thinkers certain marked features of resemblance,

and others equally marked of difference. We see their differences most

strikingly in their descendants. From Bacon lineally descended Hobbes, Locke,

Diderot, D'Alembert, Condillac, Cabanis, and our Scotch school. From

Descartes descended Spinoza, Malebranche, Leibnitz, Fichte, Schelling, and

Hegel. The inductive method predominated in one school, the deductive in the

other. These differences we shall recognize more fully later on; at present

we may fix our minds on the two great points of resemblance: 1st, the decisive

separation of philosophy from theology; 2d, the promulgation of a new method.

The separation of philosophy from theology is made emphatic in the

rejection of final causes by both Bacon and Descartes. Perhaps the most

effective of their novelties was the effort of Descartes to explain the system

of the world by matter and motion only, thus quietly setting aside all causes

and metaphysical entities which had hitherto been invoked. The hypothesis of

vortices was indeed soon disclosed to be untenable; but the scientific

attitude from which that hypothesis proceeded was never afterward

relinquished. It was a bold attempt at the application of the objective

method, and was only defective in its restriction to cosmology, and its

exclusion of biology, which was still left to the subjective method, as I

shall presently notice.

The second point on which Bacon and Descartes resemble each other is in

their conception of the results to be achieved by a totally new method. Coming

as they did on the top of the revolutionary wave which had washed away the old

methods, seeing as they saw the striking results of physical research, and

foreseeing yet more glorious conquests from the spirit which achieved those

results, they yielded themselves to the pleasant illusion that a new method

would rapidly solve all problems. Bacon, as the more magnificent and

imaginative mind, had grander visions and more enthusiastic faith; but

Descartes also firmly believed that the new method was to do wonders. Indeed,

it is interesting to note how these great intellects seem quite unconscious of

their individual superiority, and are ready to suppose that their method will

equalize all intellects. It reminds us of Sydney Smith maintaining that any

man might be witty if he tried. Descartes affirms that "it is not so

essential to have a fine understanding as to apply it rightly. Those who walk

slowly make greater progress if they follow the right road than those who run

swiftly on a wrong one." To the same effect Bacon: "A cripple on the right

path will beat a racer on the wrong one." This is true enough, but is beside

the question. Equipped with good or bad instruments, the superiority of one

worker over another is always made manifest; and it is precisely in the right

use of a good method that the scientific genius is called upon for its

delicate and patient skill.

Into the vexed questions of Bacon's conduct, both with regard to Essex

and with regard to bribery, I cannot enter here; but referring the curious to

his biographers and critics, I will simply note that he was born in 1561; was

educated at Trinity College, Cambridge, where he learned to distrust the

Aristotelianism of his masters, and planned his own vast scheme of reform;

went to Paris; sat in Parliament as member for Middlesex; was successively

appointed of the Privy Council, and lord chancellor; was created Viscount

Verulam; was impeached and condemned for corruption as a judge; and died in

the spring of 1626. "For my name and memory," said the dying man, "I leave it

to men's charitable speeches, and to foreign nations, and the next age."

Posterity has been generous; the fame of Bacon is immense. Admirers have

not always been unanimous as to his special claims; but there has been no lack

of enthusiasm, no questioning of his genius. He has been lauded for

achievements in which he had no part, and has been adorned with titles to

which he had doubtful pretensions; while his most important services have been

overlooked. But the general recognition of his greatness, and our national

pride in it, have not prevented certain attacks on his reputation, which have

been answered in a rather angry spirit; and thus from one cause and another

there is great difficulty in arriving at any candid and thorough appreciation

of the work he did. It seems to some persons that Bacon did very little in

rising against the philosophy of his day, and pointing out a new path; and to

others it seems that he did nothing of the kind. But whoever looks closely

into the writings of Bacon's predecessors will see that what now seems obvious

and trivial was then startling and important. As M. emusat felicitously says,

"Il fallait du genie pour avoir ce bon sens." And to those who deny that Bacon

did head the revolution, I would oppose not simply the testimony of nearly

three centuries, but the testimony of Gassendi, who, both as contemporary and

as foreigner, was capable of judging the effect then produced. It is indeed

apparent to anyone familiar with the writings of some of Bacon's immediate

predecessors, especially Galileo, that there was little novelty in his

denunciations of the erroneous method then popular, or in his exhortations to

pursue observation, experiment, and induction. But it is not less apparent

that he had wider and profounder views of the philosophy of method than any of

them, and that the popular opinion does not err in attributing to him the

glory of heading the new era.

In England he is commonly regarded as the "Father of Experimental

Philosophy" and the originator of the inductive method. Men profess

themselves followers of the "Baconian philosophy," sometimes confounding that

with a servile attention to facts and a most unscientific scorn of theories;

at other times implying that by the Baconian method is to be understood the

one on which science has successfully been pursued. A rigorous investigation

of Bacon's claims will disclose the truth of his own statement, that he was

rather one who sounded the trumpet-call than one who marshalled the troops. He

insisted on the importance of experiment, but he could not teach what he did

not himself understand - the experimental method. He exhorted men to study

nature; but he could not give available directions for that study. He had

fervent faith in the possible conquests of science; but never having

thoroughly mastered any one science, he was incapable of appreciating the real

conditions of research. He saw clearly enough the great truth that the

progress of research must be gradual, but he did not see what were the

necessary grades, he did not see the kind of inquiries, and the order they

must follow before discoveries could be made.

That he had really but vague and imperfect conceptions of scientific

method is decisively shown by his contemptuous rejection of Copernicus,

Galileo, and Gilbert, and by his own plan of investigation into heat. One

sentence alone would suffice to show this, namely, his sneer at Copernicus as

"a man who thinks nothing of introducing fictions of any kind into nature,

provided his calculations turn out well." Bacon did not understand, what

Copernicus profoundly saw, that the only value of an hypothesis was its

reconciliation of calculations with observations. In his plan for an

inquisition into the nature of heat, we see a total misconception of the

scientific process; not only does he set about in a laboriously erroneous way,

but he seeks that which science proclaims inaccessible, the nature of heat.

It is true that he arrives at a hypothesis which bears some resemblance to the

hypothesis now accepted, namely, that heat is a mode of motion - "an expansive

and restrained motion, modified in certain ways, and exerted in the smaller

particles of the body." But those who have been eager to credit him with an

anticipation of modern views on the strength of this definition, have

overlooked the fact that it is incapable of explaining a single process,

includes none of the ascertained laws of phenomena, and is itself an example

of the illicit generalization which Bacon elsewhere condemns. It was with

some justification, therefore, that Harvey, who knew what science was, and

knew better than most men how discoveries were made, said of him that he wrote

of science like a lord chancellor.

Indeed, it is to mistake his position and his greatness altogether to

attribute his influence on philosophy, which is undeniable, to an influence on

science which is more than questionable. Bacon was a philosopher; but because

with him philosophy, separating itself from the bondage of theology, claimed

to ally itself with science, and sought its materials in the generalities of

science, those writers who have never made a very accurate distinction between

the two, but have confounded philosophy with metaphysics, and science with

physics, have naturally regarded Bacon as the precursor of Newton, Laplace,

Faraday, and Liebig. It is in vain that critics oppose such a claim by

asserting what is undeniable, that the great discoveries in modern science

were neither made on Bacon's method nor under any direct guidance from him -

that Copernicus, Galileo, and Kepler preceded him, that Harvey and Newton

ignored him - stanch admirers have their answer ready; they know that Bacon

was the herald of the new era, and they believe that it was his trumpet-call

which animated the troops and led them to victory.

Having thus indicated his position, it will be necessary to give a brief

outline of the method which he confidently believed was to be infallible and

applicable in all inquiries. This was imperatively needed: "for let a man

look carefully into all that variety of books with which the arts and sciences

abound, he will find everywhere endless repetitions of the same thing, varying

in the method of treatment, but not new in substance, insomuch that the whole

stock, numerous as it appears at first view, proves on examination to be but

scanty. What was asserted once is asserted still, and what was a question

once is a question still, and, instead of being resolved by discussion, is

only fixed and fed."

He proposes his new method, that thereby "the intellect may be raised and

exalted and made capable of overcoming the difficulties and obscurities of

nature. The art which I introduce with this view (which I call the

'Interpretation of Nature') is a kind of logic, though the difference between

it and the ordinary logic is great, indeed immense. For the ordinary logic

professes to contrive and prepare helps and guards for the understanding, as

mine does; and in this one point they agree. But mine differs from it in

three points: viz., in the end aimed at, in the order of demonstration, and in

the starting-point of inquiry.

"But the greatest change I introduce is in the form itself of induction

and the judgments made thereby. For the induction of which the logicians

speak, which proceeds by simple enumeration, is a puerile thing; concluded at

hazard, is always liable to be upset by a contradictory instance, takes into

account only what is known and ordinary, and leads to no result. Now, what

the sciences stand in need of is a form of induction which shall analyze

experience and take it to pieces, and by a due process of exclusion and

rejection lead to an inevitable conclusion."

"Now, my method, though hard to practise, is easy to explain; and it is

this: I propose to establish progressive stages of certainty. The evidence of

sense, helped and guarded by a certain process of correction, I retain; but

the mental operation which follows the act of sense I for the most part

reject; and instead of it I open and lay out a new and certain path for the

mind to proceed in, starting directly from the simple sensuous perception."

The same dissatisfaction with mediaeval philosophy expressed itself in

Descartes. The incompetence of philosophers to solve the problems they

occupied themselves with-the anarchy which reigned in the scientific world,

where no two thinkers could agree upon fundamental points - the extravagance

of the conclusions to which some accepted premises led, determined him to seek

no more to slake his thirst at their fountains.

"And that is why, as soon as my age permitted me to quit my preceptors,"

he says, "I entirely gave up the study of letters; and resolving to seek no

other science than that which I could find in myself, or else in the great

book of the world, I employed the remainder of my youth in travel, in seeing

courts and camps, in frequenting people of diverse humors and conditions, in

collecting various experiences, and above all in endeavoring to draw some

profitable reflection from what I saw. For it seemed to me that I should meet

with more truth in the reasonings which each man makes in his own affairs, and

which, if wrong, would be speedily punished by failure, than in those

reasonings which the philosopher makes in his study, upon speculations which

produce no effect, and which are of no consequence to him, except perhaps that

he will be more vain of them the more remote they are from common-sense,

because he would then have been forced to employ more ingenuity and subtlety

to render them plausible."

For many years he led a roving, unsettled life; now serving in the army,

now making a tour, now studying mathematics in solitude, now conversing with

scientific men. One constant purpose gave unity to those various pursuits. He

was elaborating his answers to the questions which perplexed him; he was

preparing his method.

When only twenty-three he conceived the design of a reformation in

philosophy. He was at that time residing in his winter quarters at Neuburg,

on the Danube. His travels soon afterward commenced, and at the age of

thirty-three he retired into Holland, there in silence and solitude to arrange

his thoughts into a consistent whole. He remained there eight years; and so

completely did he shut himself from the world that he concealed from his

friends the very place of his residence.

When the results of this meditative solitude were given to the world in

the shape of his celebrated Discourse on Method, and his Meditations - to

which he invented replies - the sensation produced was immense. It was

evident to all men that an original thinker had arisen; and although this

originality could not but rouse much opposition, from the very fact of being

original, yet Descartes gained the day. His name became European. His

controversies were European quarrels. Charles I of England invited him over,

with the promise of a liberal appointment; and the invitation would probably

have been accepted had not the civil war broken out. He afterward received a

flattering invitation from Christina of Sweden, who had read some of his works

with great satisfaction, and wished to learn from himself the principles of

his philosophy.

He accepted it, and arrived in Stockholm in 1649. His reception was most

gratifying, and the Queen was so pleased with him as earnestly to beg him to

remain with her, and give his assistance toward the establishment of an

academy of sciences. But the delicate frame of Descartes was ill fitted for

the severity of the climate, and a cold, caught in one of his morning visits

to Christina, produced inflammation of the lungs, which carried him off.

Christina wept for him, had him interred in the cemetery for foreigners,

and placed a long eulogium upon his tomb. His remains were subsequently

(1666) carried from Sweden into France, and buried with great ceremony in Ste.

Genevieve du Mont.

Descartes was a great thinker; but having said this, we have almost

exhausted the praise we could bestow upon him as a man. In disposition he was

timid to servility. When promulgating his proofs of the existence of the

Deity, he was in evident alarm lest the Church should see something

objectionable in them. He had also written an astronomical treatise; but

hearing of the fate of Galileo, he refrained from publishing, and always used

some chicane in speaking of the world's movement. He was not a brave man, nor

was he an affectionate man. But he was even tempered, placid, and studious

not to give offense.

It has already been indicated that the great work performed by Descartes

was, like that of Bacon, the promulgation of a new method. This was rendered

necessary by their separation from the ancient philosophy and their exclusion

of authority. If inquiry is to be independent, if reason is to walk alone, in

what direction must she walk? Having relinquished the aid of the Church,

there were but two courses open: the one to tread once more in the path of the

ancients, and to endeavor by the ancient methods to attain the truth; or else

to open a new path, to invent a new method. The former was barely possible.

The spirit of the age was deeply imbued with a feeling of opposition against

the ancient methods; and Descartes himself had been painfully perplexed by the

universal anarchy and uncertainty which prevailed. The second course was

therefore chosen.

Uncertainty was the disease of the epoch. Scepticism was widespread, and

even the most confident dogmatism could offer no criterion of certitude. This

want of criterion was saw leading, in Greece, to scepticism, Epicureanism,

Stoicism, the New Academy, and finally leading the Alexandrians into the

province of faith, to escape from the dilemma. The question of a criterion

had long been the vital question of philosophy. Descartes could get no answer

to it from the doctors of his day. Unable to find firm ground on any of the

prevalent systems, distracted by doubts, mistrusting the conclusions of his

own understanding, mistrusting the evidences of his senses, he determined to

make a tabula rasa, and reconstruct his knowledge. He resolved to examine the

premises of every conclusion, and to believe nothing but upon the clearest

evidence of reason; evidence so convincing that he could not by any effort

refuse to assent to it.

He has given us the detailed history of his doubts. He has told us how

he found that he could plausibly enough doubt of everything except of his own

existence. He pushed his scepticism to the verge of self-annihilation. There

he stopped; there in self, in his consciousness, he found at last an

irresistible fact, an irreversible certainty.

Firm ground was discovered. He could doubt the existence of the external

world, and treat it as a phantasm; he could doubt the existence of a God, and

treat the belief as a superstition; but of the existing of his thinking,

doubting mind no sort of doubt was possible. He, the doubter, existed if

nothing else existed. The existence that was revealed in his own

consciousness was the primary fact, the first indubitable certainty. Hence

his famous "Cogito, ergo sum" ("I think, therefore I am").

It is somewhat curious, and, as an illustration of the frivolous verbal

disputes of philosophers, not a little instructive, that this celebrated

"Cogito, ergo sum," should have been frequently attacked for its logical

imperfection. It has been objected, from Gassendi downward, that to say, "I

think, therefore I am," is a begging of the question; since existence has to

be proved identical with thought. Certainly, if Descartes had intended to

prove his own existence by reasoning, he would have been guilty of the petitio

principii Gassendi attributes to him, viz., that the major premise, "that

which thinks exists," is assumed, not proved. But he did not intend this.

What was his object? He has told us that it was to find a starting point from

which to reason - to find an irreversible certainty. And where did he find

this? In his own consciousness. Doubt as I may, I cannot doubt of my own

existence, because my very doubt reveals to me a something which doubts. You

may call this an assumption, if you will: I will point out the fact as one

above and beyond all logic; which logic can neither prove nor disprove; but

which must always remain an irreversible certainty, and as such a fitting

basis of philosophy.

I exist. No doubt can darken such a truth; no sophism can confute this

clear principle. This is a certainty, if there be none other. This is the

basis of all science. It is in vain to ask for a proof of that which is

self-evident and irresistible. I exist. The consciousness of my existence is

to me the assurance of my existence.

Had Descartes done no more than point out this fact he would have no

claim to notice here; and we are surprised to find many writers looking upon

this "Cogito, ergo sum," as constituting the great idea in his system. Surely

it is only a statement of universal experience - an epigrammatic form given to

the common-sense view of the matter. Any clown would have told him that the

assurance of his existence was his consciousness of it; but the clown would

not have stated it so well. He would have said, "I know I exist, because I

feel that I exist."

Descartes therefore made no discovery in pointing out this fact as an

irreversible certainty. The part it plays in his system is only that of a

starting-point. It makes consciousness the basis of all truth. There is none

other possible. Interrogate consciousness, and its clear replies will be

science. Here we have a new basis and a new philosophy introduced. It was

indeed but another shape of the old formula, "Know thyself," so differently

interpreted by Thales, Socrates, and the Alexandrians; but it gave that

formula a precise signification, a thing it had before always wanted. Of

little use could it be to tell man to know himself. How is he to know

himself? By looking inward? We all do that. By examining the nature of his

thoughts? That had been done without success. By examining the process of

his thoughts? That, too, had been accomplished, and the logic of Aristotle

was the result.

The formula needed a precise interpretation; and that interpretation

Descartes gave. Consciousness, said he, is the basis of all knowledge; it is

only ground of absolute certainty. Whatever it distinctly proclaims must be

true. The process, then, is simple: examine your consciousness, and its clear

replies. Hence the vital portion of his system lies in this axiom: All clear

ideas as true: whatever is clearly and distinctly conceived is true. This

axiom he calls the foundation of all science, the rule and measure of truth.

The next step to be taken was to determine the rules for the proper

detection of these ideas; and these rules he has laid down as follows:

1. Never accept anything as true but what is evidently so; to admit

nothing but what so clearly and distinctly presents itself as true that there

can be no reason to doubt it.

2. To divide every question into as many separate questions as possible;

that each part being more easily conceived, the whole may be more intelligible

- (Analysis).

3. To conduct the examination with order, beginning by that of objects

the most simple, and therefore the easiest to be known, and ascending little

by little up to knowledge of the most complex - (Synthesis).

4. To make such exact calculations and such circumspections as to be

confident that nothing essential has been omitted.

Consciousness, being the ground of all certainty, everything of which you

are clearly and distinctly conscious must be true; everything which you

clearly and distinctively conceive exists, if the idea of it involves

existence.

In the four rules, and in this view of consciousness, we have only half

of Descartes' system; the psychological half. It was owing to the exclusive

consideration of this half that Dugald Steward was led - in controverting

Condorcet's assertion that Descartes had done more than either Galileo or

Bacon toward experimental philosophy - to say that Condorcet would have been

nearer the truth if he had pointed him out as the "Father of the Experimental

Philosophy of the Mind." Perhaps the title is just; but Condorcet's praise,

though exaggerated, was not without good foundation.

There is, in truth, another half of Descartes' system, equally important,

or nearly so: we mean the deductive method. His eminence as a mathematician

is universally recognized. He was the first to make the grand discovery of

the application of algebra to geometry; and he made this at the age of

twenty-three. The discovery that geometrical curves might be expressed by

algebraical numbers, though highly important in the history of mathematics,

only interests us here by leading us to trace his philosophical development.

He was deeply engrossed in mathematics; he saw that mathematics were capable

of a still further simplification and a far more extended application. Struck

as he was with the certitude of mathematical reasoning, he began applying the

principles of mathematical reasoning to the subject of metaphysics. His great

object was, amid the scepticism and anarchy of his contemporaries, to found a

system which should be solid and convincing. He first wished to find a basis

of certitude - a starting point: this he found in consciousness. He next

wished to find a method of certitude: this he found in mathematics.

"Those long chains of reasoning," he tell us, "all simple and easy, which

geometers use to arrive at their most difficult demonstrations, suggested to

me that all things which came within human knowledge must follow each other in

a similar chain; and that provided we abstain from admitting anything as true

which is not so, and that we always preserve in them the order necessary to

deduce one from the other, there can be none so remote to which we cannot

finally attain, nor so obscure but that we may discover them." From these

glimpses of the twofold nature of Descartes' method, it will be easy to see

into his whole system: consciousness being the only ground of certitude,

mathematics the only method of certitude.

We may say therefore that the deductive method was now completely

constituted. The whole operation of philosophy henceforth consisted in

deducing consequences. The premises had been found; the conclusions alone

were wanting. This was held to be true of physics no less than of psychology.

Thus, in his Principia, he announces his intention of giving a short account

of the principal phenomena of the world, not that we may use them as reasons

to prove anything; for he adds: "we desire to deduce effects from causes, not

from effects; but only in order that out of the innumerable effects which we

learn to be capable of resulting from the same causes, we may determine our

minds to consider these rather than others."

You Might Also Like:

World History related image
Read More

World History

Welcome to our World History section, a vast treasure trove of historical knowledge that takes you on a captivating journey through the annals of human civilization. Our collection spans a wide spectrum of topics, providing an exhaustive resource for history enthusiasts, students, and curious minds ...
Read More

A Complete History Of The European Middle Ages

The Middle Ages Date: 1992 During the decline of the Roman Empire, the migrations of a strong, rude people began to change the life of Europe. They were the German barbarians, or Teutonic tribes, who swept across the Rhine and the Danube into the empire. There they accepted Christianity. The union o...
Read More

A Day In The Life Of A Battle Of Britain Pilot

The following would have been a typical day in the life of a Battle of Britain pilot The sequences are based on the works of different authors with the exception that the names have been changed. This is just to give you an idea as to how a pilot may have spent his day at the height of the battle. ...
Read More

A General Survey Of The Slave Plantation

The American Civil War, Frederick Douglass Edited by: Robert Guisepi 2002 A General Survey of the Slave Plantation by Frederick Douglass It was generally supposed that slavery in the State of Maryland existed in its mildest form, and that it was totally divested of those harsh and terrible peculiari...
Read More

A. P. Hill

The American Civil War, A. P. Hill Edited by: Robert Guisepi 2002 b. Nov. 9, 1825, Culpeper, Va., U.S.d. April 2, 1865, Petersburg, Va. Confederate general during the U.S. Civil War who was particularly active in the fighting around Washington, D.C. His force, called the "Light Division," was cons...
Read More

Abolitionism

The American Civil War, Abolition, The Movement Edited by: Robert Guisepi 2002 There can be no doubt that antislavery, or "abolition" as it came to be called, was the nonpareil reform. Abolition was a diverse phenomenon. At one end of its spectrum was William Lloyd Garrison, an "immediatist," who de...
Read More

Abraham Lincoln

The American Civil War, Abraham Lincoln American Civil War history with slideshows, photos, music, major battles like Gettysburg as well as personalities like Lincoln, Grant, Lee and the Black Regiments Edited by: Robert Guisepi 2002 He was an unusual man in many ways. One minute he would wrestle wi...
Read More

Absolutism

European Absolutism And Power Politics Introduction Louis XIV (1643-1715) of France is remembered best as a strong-willed monarch who reportedly once exclaimed to his fawning courtiers, "L'etat, c'est moi" (I am the state). Whether or not he really said these words, Louis has been regarded by histor...
Read More

Absolutism As A System

Absolutism As A System L'Etat, C'Est Moi Date: 1998 Absolutism As A System Unlimited royal authority, as advocated by Bossuet and Hobbes, was the main characteristic of absolutism. It was demonstrated most obviously in political organization but also served to integrate into government most econom...
Read More

Absolutism, Case Against

The Case Against AbsolutismAuthor: Wallbank;Taylor;Bailkey;Jewsbury;Lewis;HackettDate: 1992The Case Against AbsolutismThe Enlightenment's highest achievement was the development of a tightlyorganized philosophy, purportedly based on scientific principles andcontradicting every argument for absolute ...
Read More

Accession Of Solomon

Accession Of Solomon Author: Milman, Henry Hart Accession Of Solomon B.C. 1017 Introduction After many weary years of travail and fighting in the wilderness and the land of Canaan, the Jews had at last founded their kingdom, with Jerusalem as the capital. Saul was proclaimed the first king; afterwa ...
Read More

Acropolis

A History of Ancient Greece The Glory That Was Greece Author: Jewsbury, Lewis Date: 1992 The Acropolis Acropolis (Greek akros,"highest"; polis,"city"), term originally applied to any fortified natural stronghold or citadel in ancient Greece. Primarily a place of refuge, the typical acropolis was con...
Read More

Aegean Civilization

A History of Ancient Greece Author: Robert Guisepi Date: 1998 AEGEAN CIVILIZATION The earliest civilization in Europe appeared on the coasts and islands of the Aegean Sea. This body of water is a branch of the Mediterranean Sea. It is bounded by the Greek mainland on the west, Asia Minor (now Turkey...
Read More

Aemilius Paulus

AEMILIUS PAULUS by Plutarch Almost all historians agree that the Aemilii were one of the ancient and patrician houses in Rome; and those authors who affirm that king Numa was pupil to Pythagoras, tell us that the first who gave the name to his posterity was Mamercus, the son of Pythagoras, who, for ...
Read More

Africa In The Age Of The Slave Trade

Africa And The Africans In The Age Of The Atlantic Slave Trade Various Authors Edited By: R. A. GuisepiAfrican Societies, Slavery, And The Slave TradeEuropeans in the age of the slave trade sometimes justified enslavementof Africans by pointing out that slavery already existed on that continent.Howe...
Read More